THE FORGOTTEN ASPECTS OF TIME
Fascinating as the results of Einstein’s two relativity theories are, many of them are not directly relevant to my main theme. Popular accounts that cover topics I omit are recommended in the section on Further Reading. My aim in Part 3 is to show how Einstein’s approach to relativity led him to an explicit theory of simultaneity but an implicit theory of duration. It is the latter that is important for this book, but it never got properly treated in relativity. The point is that remarkable facts about duration, as revealed through the clocks of different observers, follow inescapably from the definition of simultaneity and the relativity principle. Einstein did not need to create a theory of clocks and duration from first principles in order to learn some facts about them: they already followed from his two primary postulates.
BOX 10 The Impossible Becomes Possible
Figure 26 The horizontal and inclined strips, in which time increases vertically and the horizontal represents one space dimension, show the histories of two physically identical rods moving uniformly relative to each other. For Bob and Alice, points on the continuous line
The method Einstein used to create his relativity theories is an important factor. During the nineteenth century, mainly through the development of thermodynamics, physicists began to distinguish between, on the one hand, theories of the world in terms of truly basic laws and constituents (e.g. atoms and fields) and, on the other hand, so-called principle theories. In the latter, no attempt would be made to give an ultimate theory of things. Instead, the idea was to seek principles that seemed to hold with great generality and include them in the foundations of the description of phenomena. The repeated failures of all attempts to build perpetual-motion machines, of which two distinct types could be envisaged, became the basis of the first and second laws of thermodynamics. In the form in which it was developed on this basis, thermodynamics was a theory of the second kind – a principle theory.
In contrast, Lorentz’s combined theory of the electromagnetic field, electric charges and the aether was basically a theory of the first kind – it aspired to a fundamental description of the world in terms of its ultimate constituents. Einstein deliberately decided not to follow such a path in his own work on electrodynamics, from which the special theory of relativity emerged. He based it as far as possible on general principles. The fact is that Max Planck’s quantum discoveries (Box 1) and Einstein’s own development of them a few months before the relativity paper had persuaded Einstein that something very strange was afoot. Despite his admiration for Maxwell’s equations, he felt sure that they could not be the true laws of electromagnetism because they completely failed to explain the quantum effects. He had no confidence in his ability to find correct alternatives. Then, and to the end of his days, Einstein found the quantum baffling. He felt deeply that it was a huge mystery. By comparison, relativity (the special theory at least) was almost child’s play.
It was this attitude that largely shaped Einstein’s strategy in approaching the problem of the electromagnetic aether. He resolved to make no attempt at a detailed description of microscopic phenomena. Instead, he would rely on the relativity principle, for which there seemed to be strong experimental support, and make as few additional assumptions as possible. In the event, he was able to limit these to his assumption about the nature of light propagation. This was the one part of Maxwell’s scheme that he felt reasonably confident would survive the quantum revolution.