1 One of Tolstoy’s Russian critics, M. M. Rubinshtein, referred to above (9/1), 80 ff., says that every science employs
2 [‘The obscure through the more obscure’, i.e. explaining something obscure in terms of something even more obscure.]
1
2 See V. B. Shklovsky, op. cit. (7/3), chapters 7 and 8, and also K. Pokrovsky, ‘Istochniki romana “Voina i mir” ’, in Obninsky and Polner, op. cit. (9/1), 113–28.
1
2 ‘Neskol′ko slov po povodu knigi: “Voina i mir”’ (1868), T xvi 5–16.
1
1 op. cit. (8/2), 34, 40.
2 N. I. Kareev, ‘Istoricheskaya filosofiya v “Voine i mire”’,
3 ibid. 230; cf.
1 B. M. Eikhenbaum,
2 Here the paradox appears once more; for the ‘infinitesimals’, whose integration is the task of the ideal historian, must be reasonably uniform to make this operation possible; yet the sense of ‘reality’ consists in the sense of their unique differences.
1 In our day French existentialists, for similar psychological reasons, have struck out against all explanations as such because they are a mere drug to still serious questions, short-lived palliatives for wounds which are unbearable but must be borne, above all not denied or ‘explained’; for all explaining is explaining away, and that is a denial of the given – the existent – the brute facts.
1 For example, both Shklovsky (
1 ‘On n’a pas rendu justice à Rousseau […]. J’ai lu tout Rousseau, oui, tous les vingt volumes, y compris le
1 ibid. (‘il n’y a point de panache à la guerre’).
1 See Adolfo Omodeo,
2 ‘Chitayu Maistr′a’, T xlviii 66.
1 See Eikhenbaum, op. cit. (40/ 1), i 308–17.
2
3 ibid. vol. 1, part 1, chapter 3, T x 13–16; W 10–13. For the note see T xiii 687.
1 ibid. vol. 4, part 3, chapter 19, T xii 167; W 1182.
2 S. P. Zhikharev,